Art as viewed by philosophy is a fascinating and complex topic. Philosophers have approached art from various perspectives, including aesthetics, metaphysics, and ethics. Aestheticians explore the nature of beauty, the role of art in human experience, and the criteria for evaluating artworks. Some philosophers delve into the metaphysical aspects of art, considering questions of creativity, representation, and the relationship between the artwork and reality. Additionally, ethics comes into play as philosophers examine the moral and social dimensions of art, such as the responsibilities of artists and the impact of art on society. Overall, the philosophical exploration of art offers rich insights into the nature of creativity, perception, and the human condition.

Plato (428 – 347 BCE)

art-as-viewed-by-philosophy
Plato 428 347 BCE

Plato, the ancient Greek philosopher, made profound contributions to the philosophy of art through his dialogues, most notably in “The Republic” and “Ion.” His views on art were shaped by a profound skepticism towards its ability to represent truth and virtue. Plato’s exploration of art primarily revolves around two key theories: the theory of mimesis (art as imitation) and the theory of the dangers of art. In examining these theories, we gain insights into Plato’s philosophical concerns about the nature and impact of artistic representation.

1. Art is Imitation

In “The Republic,” Plato presents his theory of mimesis (art as imitation) through the character of Socrates. The term “mimesis” refers to the act of imitation or representation. According to Plato, art, particularly poetry and drama, involves a mimetic process wherein artists imitate the physical world without understanding the underlying truths. He argues that artists create a copy of reality, which is already an imperfect representation of the ideal Forms or essences that exist in the realm of the Forms.

For Plato, the world perceived through the senses is a mere shadow or illusion of the true reality. In this context, art becomes a copy of a copy, distancing itself further from the ultimate reality. In “The Republic,” Plato illustrates this concept through the famous Allegory of the Cave, where prisoners mistake shadows on the wall for reality. Similarly, he contends that art captivates people with illusions, leading them away from the pursuit of genuine knowledge and truth.

Plato’s concern with mimesis is deeply rooted in his philosophical conviction that only the Forms, or ideal and unchanging realities, can provide true knowledge. Art, as a mimetic representation, falls short of capturing these transcendent truths. Consequently, Plato argues that art is deceptive and misleading, diverting individuals from the pursuit of philosophical understanding and moral virtue.

While acknowledging the aesthetic appeal of art, Plato contends that it lacks a moral and intellectual foundation. He criticizes the poets for their ability to evoke emotions without imparting genuine wisdom. The emotional responses generated by art, according to Plato, are superficial and irrational, leading individuals away from rational contemplation of the higher truths.

2. Art is Dangerous

In addition to the theory of mimesis, Plato expresses concerns about the potentially harmful effects of art on individuals and society. In “The Republic,” he introduces the concept of the “noble lie,” which involves the use of myths and tales to shape the behavior and beliefs of the citizens in his ideal state.

Plato argues that poets and artists, by crafting engaging narratives, have the power to shape the moral and social fabric of a community. However, he is wary of the influence of art on the soul, particularly when it comes to representing negative or harmful behavior. Plato asserts that art has the potential to corrupt the minds of the citizens, as it can glorify immoral actions or present a distorted view of virtue.

In particular, Plato is critical of tragic poetry and drama, which often depict characters undergoing suffering and misfortune. While acknowledging the emotional catharsis that tragedy provides, he contends that it can also evoke irrational and disruptive emotions. Plato worries that the audience, by sympathizing with the tragic hero’s suffering, may inadvertently embrace negative emotions and attitudes.

Moreover, Plato suggests that the portrayal of the gods in poetry can be problematic. He argues that poets often depict the gods engaged in immoral behavior, setting a bad example for the citizens. Plato’s concern is not merely with the content of the myths but also with their potential to shape the ethical values and beliefs of the community.

In “Ion,” another dialogue of Plato, the dangers of artistic inspiration are explored through the character Ion, a rhapsode who claims to be inspired by the Muses. Socrates challenges Ion’s understanding of inspiration, arguing that the rhapsode is not genuinely knowledgeable but merely possessed by a divine frenzy. This dialogue further underscores Plato’s suspicion of the emotional and irrational elements associated with artistic inspiration.

Thus, Plato’s theories on art as imitation and the dangers of art reveal his deep-seated skepticism about the capacity of art to convey truth and contribute to moral and intellectual development. His emphasis on the primacy of the Forms as the source of genuine knowledge underscores his belief that art, being a mimetic representation of the sensory world, is inherently deficient in capturing the ultimate reality.

Moreover, Plato’s concerns about the dangers of art reflect a broader worry about the potential influence of artistic representation on individual and societal values. He contends that art has the power to shape emotions, beliefs, and behaviors, and thus, it must be approached with caution. While acknowledging the aesthetic and emotional appeal of art, Plato remains steadfast in his conviction that the pursuit of truth and virtue should take precedence over the seductive illusions of artistic representation.

Plato’s theories on art have left a lasting impact on the history of aesthetics and continue to stimulate discussions about the role and value of art in philosophical inquiry. While subsequent thinkers have offered alternative perspectives, Plato’s critical examination of art as imitation and as a potential source of moral and intellectual danger remains a foundational part of the ongoing dialogue between philosophy and the arts.

Aristotle (384 – 322 BCE)

art-as-viewed-by-philosophy
Aristotle 384 322 BCE

Aristotle’s contributions to the philosophy of art, as outlined in his work “Poetics,” are foundational to our understanding of aesthetics and artistic expression. In his exploration of various art forms, Aristotle provides insights into the nature, purpose, and effects of art that continue to shape discussions on creativity and representation. Here, we will delve into some key aspects of Aristotle’s views on art.

1. Mimesis and Representation

Aristotle, like his predecessor Plato, acknowledges the concept of mimesis, which refers to the imitation or representation of the external world through art. However, Aristotle takes a more nuanced approach, considering mimesis not as a mere replication but as a transformative and creative act. He argues that art is an imitation of nature, capturing the essential qualities and actions of the real world. Aristotle values the artist’s ability to select and organize elements from reality to create a representation that resonates with the audience.

2. Catharsis and Emotional Purification

One of Aristotle’s most renowned contributions to the philosophy of art is his concept of catharsis, particularly in the context of tragedy. Aristotle contends that tragedy, through its representation of fear and pity, elicits an emotional catharsis in the audience. While he does not precisely define catharsis, it is commonly understood as a purgation or purification of emotions. Tragedy allows spectators to experience a release of pent-up emotions, providing a therapeutic and purifying effect. This emotional cleansing, according to Aristotle, contributes to the enjoyment and educational value of tragic art.

3. The Unity of Plot

Aristotle places great emphasis on the structure of a dramatic work, particularly the importance of a unified plot. In his view, a well-constructed plot should have a beginning, middle, and end, forming a cohesive and complete whole. This unity of action, where every element contributes to the central narrative, is essential for the audience to experience a sense of closure and satisfaction. Aristotle’s insistence on unity reflects his broader philosophical belief in the orderliness and harmony of the natural world.

4. Hamartia and Tragic Hero

Aristotle introduces the concept of “hamartia” in his analysis of tragedy. Hamartia, often translated as a tragic flaw, refers to a character’s error in judgment that leads to their downfall. According to Aristotle, the tragic hero is a character of noble stature who undergoes a reversal of fortune due to their hamartia. This tragic hero’s journey, marked by both virtue and imperfection, engages the audience emotionally and intellectually. Aristotle’s exploration of hamartia adds depth to his understanding of character development and contributes to the enduring appeal of tragic narratives.

5. Epic vs. Tragedy

In “Poetics,” Aristotle draws a distinction between epic poetry and tragedy, highlighting their respective structures and purposes. While both involve imitation and narrative, Aristotle identifies key differences. Epic poetry, exemplified by works like Homer’s “Iliad” and “Odyssey,” tends to be more expansive, covering a broader range of characters and events. Tragedy, on the other hand, is more focused and concentrates on a specific set of characters and actions. Aristotle’s comparative analysis sheds light on the unique qualities and functions of these two major forms of artistic expression in ancient Greece.

6. Purpose and Moral Education

Aristotle sees the purpose of art as multifaceted. While recognizing its capacity to provide pleasure and entertainment, he goes beyond mere aesthetics, asserting that art also serves an educational function. Through the representation of virtuous and flawed characters, art can inspire contemplation on ethical principles and contribute to the audience’s moral understanding. Aristotle believes that art has the power to shape perceptions, evoke emotions, and ultimately contribute to the moral and intellectual development of individuals and society.

7. Imitation of Human Action

Central to Aristotle’s philosophy of art is the idea that its primary subject matter is human action. He argues that art imitates life, capturing the complexities and nuances of human experience. Through the imitation of characters and their actions, art provides insights into the intricacies of moral decision-making, the consequences of human behavior, and the universal aspects of the human condition. Aristotle’s focus on the representation of human action underscores the potential of art to engage with and illuminate various aspects of human existence.

In conclusion, Aristotle’s “Poetics” stands as a foundational text in the philosophy of art, offering a comprehensive exploration of the principles that govern artistic expression. His nuanced understanding of mimesis, the emotional power of catharsis, the importance of plot unity, and the complexities of character development continue to inform contemporary discussions on aesthetics. Aristotle’s enduring influence is evident in the ongoing exploration of the purpose and effects of art across various artistic forms and cultural contexts.

Immanuel Kant (1724 – 1804)

art-as-viewed-by-philosophy

Immanuel Kant, a philosopher from the past, had some interesting ideas about art, especially when it comes to what we find beautiful. According to Kant, beauty is not something in an object; it’s more about how we feel when we look at it.

Kant talked about “disinterested pleasure,” which means enjoying something without expecting anything in return. When we call something beautiful, we’re saying it gives us a good feeling just by looking at it, without needing anything else.

He thought that our imagination and understanding work together when we find something beautiful. Our imagination freely plays around with the object, and our understanding brings some order to it. When these two work together nicely, we experience beauty.

Kant also introduced the idea of the “sublime.” This is when something is so big or powerful that it’s almost scary. It’s like the feeling you get when you look at a massive mountain or a powerful storm – it’s not just pretty; it gives you a mix of awe and fear.

When it comes to art, Kant believed it’s special because it’s not just about pretty things in nature. Artists create something new, and this creation has its own value. He called this the “autonomy of art.” Simply put, art is valuable not just because it looks nice, but because it’s made with a purpose.

Kant also had this idea of a “genius” – not a super-smart person, but someone who’s really good at making unique and special art. A genius, according to Kant, can create things that are original and meaningful, going beyond rules and conventions.

Now, here’s where it gets interesting. Kant believed that even though our judgments about beauty are personal, there’s still something universal about them. When many people with good taste agree that something is beautiful, it’s like there’s a shared understanding, even if we each have our own feelings.

He talked about “subjective taste” and “universal taste.” Subjective taste is our personal preference – what each of us likes. But Kant argued that there’s also a universal taste, where many people can agree that something is beautiful. It’s like having a common understanding of what’s nice, even if we all have our unique opinions.

Kant’s ideas about art are about how we feel and think when we see something beautiful or powerful. Beauty, for him, is a mix of imagination and understanding, and art is valuable because it’s created with a purpose. His thoughts on the sublime, the genius, and the difference between subjective and universal taste add more layers to his simple yet profound philosophy of art.

author avatar
Maria Lorena Assistant Professor II

Categorized in:

Art,